|
|
|
 |
Law and Norm: Science and Biopolitics through a Foucauldian perspective [1]
ThanasisLagios*
Abstract
This essay is an attempt to describe the
genealogy, that is, the historical emergence of the judicio-medical
apparatus of scientific discourse that is known as “criminology”, in order to
raise epistemological questions concerning its conditions of possibility and
its conditions of production in the context of modern western societies. More
specifically, the main question that should be asked is if the discourse and
practices of criminology belong exclusively in the area or field of Law and
Justice or whether they belong also and inevitably in the area or field of the
Norm and Medicine.Thus, a historical–philosophical
survey should examine the conditions of possibility and the consequences of
this judicio-medical apparatus, since its emergence
and its production are based not only on the concept of Law but also on the
concept of the Norm.
Keywords: Criminology, Norm, Law, Biopolitics, Foucault
Introduction
Around 1807 – 8, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel
(1770 – 1831) set rather clearly and plainly a – very simple in form, but
deeply serious in its content – question: “Who thinks abstractly?” And he gave
the following short, sharp and surprising answer: “The uneducated, not the
educated”. Subsequently, Hegel makes all speed to give a concrete example of
such abstract thinking: “A murderer is led to the place of execution. For the
common populace he is nothing but a murderer. Ladies perhaps remark that he is
a strong, handsome, interesting man. The populace finds this remark terrible:
What? A murderer handsome? How can one think so
wickedly and call a murderer handsome; no doubt, you yourselves are something
not much better! This is the corruption of morals that is prevalent in the
upper classes, a priest may add, knowing the bottom of things and human hearts.
One who knows men traces the development of the criminal's mind: he finds in
his history, in his education, a bad family relationship between his father and
mother, some tremendous harshness after this human being had done some minor
wrong, so he became embittered against the social order — a first reaction to
this that in effect expelled him and henceforth did not make it possible for
him to preserve himself except through crime. — There may be people who will
say when they hear such things: he wants to excuse this murderer!”[2]
Thus, if, according to the
Hegelian perspective and perception of things, the “one who knows men” traces
the formation and development of the criminal in every aspect and fold of his
life and personality, is the single and only example of non-abstract, that is,
of non-metaphysical but of concrete and scientific thinking, then we should not
be surprised by the fact that, even before the end of the nineteenth century,
this very example was the model for Criminology. As it was aptly written, in
1893, by the Austrian Professor of Criminology and Law, Hans Gustav Adolf Gross
(1847 – 1915), in his Handbuch für Untersuchungsrichterals System der Kriminalistik(1893), an investigator should acquire a deep and
profound knowledge of human behaviour by noting down the individuals that
surround him: “To this end everything
in life can be utilised—every conversation, every concise statement, every word
thrown out by chance, every action, every aspiration, every trait of character,
every item of conduct, every look or gesture, (…)”.[3]
Therefore, the question
that arises is how from a phenomenology of the spirit have we come into a
phenomenology of the criminal?[4] How,
during modernity, have western societies been distanced from the radical
critique to the metaphysical thinking of the abstract and reached the
scientific worship of the concrete? Shortly, how have we found ourselves in a
great distance from the abstract and moral way of thinking that characterized not only the common populace but also the ladies of the upper class
who, according to the Hegelian example, equally abstractly see the criminal
either as a moral monster or as an interestingly peculiar being? And how have
we managed to reach the concrete, profound, that is, scientific knowledge of
the biography and the thoroughly detailed mapping of the criminal personality?
How, that is, at which price and through which means? Do we still remain in the
field of Right and Law, when we refer to crime or do we
actually approach the field of Medicine and the Norm? Could there be any kind
of criminology that has not already been a forensic science? These questions
might be heard as peculiar and untimely at a time, during which the
identification of the criminal is taking place inside the police lab, before he
even sits accused in the dock, but they have a profound and great historical
and theoretical significance for the understanding not only of the past but
also of the present of our societies and of the formation and construction not
only of Criminology but also of Medicine.
Conditions
of possibility of a judicio-medical domain
Therefore, it is time to be more concrete. In
1831, the Phrenological Society of Paris was founded,
in order to promote the scientific ideas of the Austrian neuroanatomist and
physiologist Franz Joseph Gall (1758 – 1828), who believed that it was
absolutely possible to acquire knowledge of the personality and both mental and
moral faculties of an individual on the basis of the external shape of its
skull. The examining method called cranioscopy,
according to Gall permitted the identification of up to 27 different
fundamental inclinations or tendencies that are abutted to the different
regions of the brain. The empirical affirmation of his phrenological theory had taken place in various prisons in Germany, around 1805, as he found
there through cranioscopies that all the thieves were
inscribed at the maximum rate – that
is, at an abnormal rate – the normal,
in other respects, tendency towards greed. Gall’s cranioscopies on convicted criminals inaugurated the medical explanation and interpretation
of a crime and provided a scientific guide for the legal treatment of
criminals. The path to Cesare Lombroso (born Ezechia Marco Lombroso; 1835 – 1909) was royally opened and the latter’s
“born criminal” (reo nato) could make his first steps.[5]
Nonetheless, there was a
scientific path that was plotted in a parallel line. Psychiatry and its
scientific discourse had already begun to fight against the primacy of legal
discourse in the field of justice, as the case of farmer Pierre Rivière eloquently shows. Let us remind ourselves that in
1972 Foucault in his annual seminar at the Collège de
France with a small group of attendants, including Robert Castel and Gilles Deleuze,[6] discovered and studied the archives of an extraordinary case, where on 3 June
1835, the 23-year old Rivière premeditatedly and
cold-bloodily murdered his mother, who was six months pregnant, as well as his
sister and his brother and then surrendered himself to police, and there he
wrote his memoir, in which through a remarkable style of writing he confesses
and describes his crimes with no remorse or regret. Rivière's trial became a scene where the confrontation between the judicial and the
medical discourse concerning its case took place. Foucault and his
collaborators managed to find and published Rivière’s own hand-written account of the case and Foucault stated simply: “I think the
reason we decided to publish these documents was to draw a map, so to speak, of
these combats, to reconstruct these confrontations and battles, to rediscover
the interaction of those discourses as weapons of attack and defence in the
relations of power and knowledge”.[7]
These combats, these
confrontations and battles had already begun in 1825, as Jean-Étienne Dominique Esquirol’s (1772 – 1840) student, Etienne-Jean Georget (1795 – 1828), based his ideas on Philippe Pinel’s (1745 – 1826) concept of “manie sans délire” (insanity without delusion), in order to bring into question certain
judicial verdicts concerning homicides and to suggest a more scientifically
appropriate explanation and interpretation of the “homicidal monomania”, that
is, of a situation where there is the certain existence of “a single
pathological preoccupation in an otherwise sound mind”.[8] In
Britain, James Cowles Prichard (1786 – 1848) was referring to “moral insanity”,
emphasizing the fact that ‘‘there is scarcely an act in the catalogue of human
crimes which has not been imitated . . . by this disease’’.[9] Finally,
in 1832 the concept of “extenuating circumstances” was introduced into the
penal code, although since 1810, in terms of the famous Article 64, the penal
code allowed that in the case when the individual is in a state of dementia
while the crime is committed, then there is no crime
or offense. According to Michel Foucault (1926 – 1984), “thus, there is the
gradual elaboration of that kind of medico-judicial continuum whose effects and
principal form of institutionalization are seen in expert medico-legal
opinion”.[10]
Nevertheless, we should
mention that this medico-legal continuum, which seems to emerge rather abruptly
in the first decades of the nineteenth century has deep and strong historical
roots in western societies, as it replaced the political order and function of
power in the Middle Ages – coded as Pax et Justitia –
with a more complicated schema that included in the first place, between the
fifteenth and seventeenth centuries, the maintenance of order and the
organization of enrichment, while on the next level, during the eighteenth
century “we find a further function emerging, that of a disposition of society
as a milieu of physical well-being, health, and optimal longevity. The exercise
of these three latter functions – order, enrichment, and health – is assured
less through a single apparatus than by an ensemble of multiple regulations and
institutions which in the eighteenth century take the generic name of ‘police’.
Down to the end of the ancient régime, the term ‘police’
does not signify (at least, not exclusively) the institution of police in the
modern sense; ‘police’ is the ensemble of mechanisms serving to ensure order,
the properly channelled growth of wealth, and the conditions of preservation of
health “in general”.[11] Foucault reminds us that the emergence, formation, and establishment of this
ensemble of mechanisms, known under the term ‘police’, began as a utopia in
1611 via Louis Turquet de Mayerne (1550?– 1618) with his work Aristo-democratic
Monarchy (La monarchie aristodemocratique, ou Le gouvernement composé et meslé des trois formes de legitimes republiques), and continued as a political program via
Nicolas Delamare’s (1639 – 1723) Treatise of the Police (Traité de la Police, 1705 - 1738), in order to end up as an academic
discipline with Johann Heinrich Gottlob Justi (1717 -
1771), one of the leading German political economists and founder of Cameralism, the writer of Elements of Police (Grundsätze der Polizeywissenschaft, 1756), where he describes Polizeiwissenschaft “as at once an art of government and a method for the analysis of a population
living on a territory”.[12] Of
course, Justi was not only one of the leading German political economists and founder of Cameralism, but was also the director of police in
Gottingen in 1755. Thus, he had definitely paved the way to the formation and
the establishment of the power–knowledge nexus, as “[w]hile he was arresting beggars and chasing down rowdy students, Justi also founded a periodical, the Göttingische Policey-Amts Nachrichten. He
dedicated it to the improvement of the Nahrungsstand, a term he used to denote society’s productive
classes—its miners, farmers, manufacturers, merchants, and shopkeepers. It was
the central organizing category of his police–cameralist program”.[13]As Wakefield observes concerning Justi and the so-called “police–science”: ‘Police–Science’
(Policeywissenschaft), the carrying card of
every universal cameralist, involved the ‘knowledge
and ability to maintain and increase the total wealth of the state.’ Everything
followed from this. It went without saying, of course, that every true cameralist kept meticulous books and observed tireless
diligence. ‘Forgetfulness, mistakes, errors, the usual excuses of disorderly
and careless people, have no place in fiscal affairs’.[14] The similarities in structure, function and order between this police-science
belonging in the field of German Cameralism and the
apparatus of Panopticon, which belongs to the spirit
of British Utilitarianism, are striking, as Foucault showed in Discipline and Punish: “This enclosed,
segmented space, observed at every point, in which the individuals are inserted
in a fixed place, in which the slightest movements are supervised, in which all
events are recorded, in which an uninterrupted work of writing links the centre
and periphery, in which power is exercised without division, according to a
continuous hierarchical figure, in which every individual is constantly
located, examined and distributed among the living beings, the sick and the dead
– all this constitutes a compact model of the disciplinary mechanism”.[15] Furthermore, from a philosophical perspective the plain, explicit and predicative remarks concerning police made
in 1797 by one of the most famous representatives and founding figures of
German Idealism, that is, Johann Gottlieb Fichte (1762 – 1814), who at least
for once abandoned his notorious obscure and perplexed prose, are historically illuminating: “The
principal maxim of every well-constituted police power must be the following:
every citizen must be readily identifiable, wherever necessary, as this or that
particular person. Police officers must be able to establish the identity of
every subject”. Chamayou very aptly and astutely
remarks that the difference between the disciplinary model of Panopticon and the model of control, that is, the
difference between discipline and security, that Fichte seems to propose
through the obligatory use of passports: “Everyone must always carry a passport
with him, issued by the nearest authority and containing a precise description
of his person; this applies to everyone, regardless of class or rank. [..]
Since merely verbal descriptions of a person always remain ambiguous, it might
be good if important persons (who therefore can afford it as well) were to
carry accurate portraits in their passports, rather than descriptions”.[16]
Consequently, these
historical transformations and mutations that took place on the point of
convergence of power and knowledge, of politics and science, were inscribed in
a telling and significant concept: “The concept of Medizinschepolizei, medical
police, which appeared in 1764, implied much more than a simply mortality and
birth census”.[17] Police-science is coextensive with the rise of mercantilism, the market town
and industrial capitalism. As Foucault remarks, ‘To police’, ‘to urbanize’: (…)
to police and to urbanize is the same thing. (…) Police and commerce, police
and urban development, and police and the development of all the activities of
the market in the broad sense, constitute an essential unity … [T]he market
town became the model of state intervention in men’s lives. I think this is the
fundamental fact of the seventeenth century, at any rate the fundamental fact
characterizing the birth of police in the seventeenth century”.[18] However, as we hope to show in what follows, Foucault does not simply or
diametrically oppose discipline to security; rather, he tries to show the
historical interrelation and interdependence of these two modes of power: “So
we should not see things as the replacement of a society of sovereignty by a
society of discipline by a society, say, of government. In fact we have a
triangle: sovereignty, discipline, and governmental management, which has population as its main target and apparatuses of
security as its essential mechanism”.[19] Moreover, Foucault does not simply or diametrically oppose law to the norm, but
attempts to show their interrelation and correlation: “I do not mean to say
that the law fades into the background or that the institutions of justice tend
to disappear, but rather that the law operates more and more as a norm, and
that the judicial institution is increasingly incorporated into a continuum of
apparatuses (medical, administrative, and so on) whose functions are for the
most part regulatory”.[20] The
consequences in both epistemological and political level were unprecedented.
In 1833 the Section of
Statistics of the British Association for the Advancement of Science was
founded under the guidance of a Belgian mathematician and astronomer named Lambert Adolphe Jacques Quetelet (1796 – 1874), known as the
“patriarch of statistics”. Quetelet following the
famous philosopher, mathematician and early political scientist Marie Jean Antoine Nicolas de Caritat, marquis de Condorcet known as Nicolas de
Condorcet (1743 – 1794) and his suggestion that society is consisted of
homogeneous individuals, equal under the law and consequently subject to the
mathematical laws that govern any social mechanism, set off to apply
mathematical analyses on the demographic data that were presented by the first
census of Parisian Population, which took place in 1817. The main target for
this census was the recording and the construction of an archive concerning the
causes of death. This census took place under the auspices of the Royal Medical
Academy and the guidance of an ex-military physician named Louis René Villermé (1782 – 1863), who used to make statistical
surveys in the prisons all over France.[21] These
data and this series of information proved to be extremely useful for Quetelet, as they were going to be the raw material of his
mathematical analyses of the social phenomena through the curve of normal
frequency distribution and the concept of the “average man” (home moyen).
The latter coincided with the statistical average, in regard with both its
mental and its physical characteristics. As Quetelet eloquently and rather clearly put it, “the determination of the average man is
not merely a matter of speculation; it may be of the most important service to
the science of man and the social system…The average man, indeed, is in a
nation what the centre of gravity is in a body”.[22] Any
behaviour or conduct in the field of sexual relationships or delinquency
diverged from the statistical mean was, on the one hand, condemnable and, on
the other hand, could be predicted or foreseen with the same level of accuracy
as in the case of the planetary motions.[23] The
fact that the number of committed suicides varied each year from 1826 to 1831,
between a minimum of 1,542 and a maximum of 2,048, the number of homicides 205
and 266, respectively, and the number of crimes against individuals varied from
1,666 to 2,046, has given the chance to Quetelet to
write: “Sad condition of humanity! The share of prisons, chains, and the
scaffold appears fixed with as much probability as the revenues of state. We
are able to enumerate in advance how many individuals will stain their hands
with the blood of their fellow creatures, how many will be forgers, how many
poisoners, pretty nearly as one can enumerate in advance the births and deaths
which must take place.”[24] Conviction rates of criminals were equally predictable, with guilty verdicts
varying between a low of 54% in 1826 and a high of 62% in 1831.[25] As Ian
Hacking suggests, “the avalanche of numbers after 1820 revealed an astonishing
regularity in statistics of crime, suicide, workers’ sickness, epidemics,
biological facts. Mathematicians attempted an analysis of such phenomena. The
great applied mathematician Siméon Denis Poisson
(1781 – 1840) invented the term ‘law of large numbers’ in 1835 as the name of a
mathematical fact that irregularities in mass phenomena would fade out if
enough data were collected. Although the term ‘law of large numbers’ is
standard in probability mathematics, Poisson’s first usage was in connection
with the analysis of jury trials”.[26] This
fetishism of numbers, especially of those concerning the calculation and
assessment of criminality or mortality, and which was institutionalised by and
through the state censuses, which during the 1820s had swept Western Europe and
the U.S.A., is fully and clearly expressed in all its splendour in the face of
the lawyer André Michel Guerry (1802 – 1866), who
during 1832–1864 analysed 21,132 cases of homicides and classified them in
4,478 classes of motives that were adopted by the police.[27] Moreover, on 2 July 1832, Guerry presented
statistical maps of France, where criminality was divided according to region,
age, gender, and season of year and was depicted, introducing the use of the
contemporary methods of geographical profiling of criminals by Scotland Yard or
FBI.[28] In
order to give an idea of the width and amplitude of the statistical and
mathematical scan of population, it suffices to say that whereas in 1870 the
census data of the U.S.A. were published in three volumes, the immediate next,
that took place just a decade later, were published in 22 volumes consisting of
21,000 pages.[29]
However, let us leave aside
for the moment the field of medical theories and mathematics and turn our
attention to the field of the more palpable and tangible technical discoveries.
At least, this was the choice made by the editors of The Edinburgh Philosophical Journal, and definitely they were
rewarded, as in 1836 the chemist James Marsh (1794 – 1846) discovered and
published an effective technique for the detection of the most popular or
“trendy” poison, from the perspective of murderers, namely, of arsenic. The
Marsh test, as it has been called ever since, could detect a quantity equal to
the 1/50 of the milligram in a specimen taken from the hair or the bones of the
dead, if there was any suspicion of poisoning. After several vociferous and
deafening judicial and police successes thanks to the Marsh test, the frequency
of use of arsenic was significantly reduced and the basic principles of the
test are in use and considered valid up till now. Under these circumstances, we
can easily understand the non-philosophical enthusiasm and the frivolous
eagerness shown by the editorial board of the Pharmaceutical Journal, when in an issue that appeared in 1841,
they exulted at the good news by claiming that the kind of murder that seemed
to “threaten the destruction of the very bonds of society”, had now, “happily
been vanished from the world” and that arsenic instead of threatening the
public now “there is none so dangerous to the criminal”, as the dead “are now
become the witnesses whom poisoners have most to fear”.[30]
Why did we call the haste
reaction of the Pharmaceutical Journal non-philosophical? If we pay attention and take a closer look to the three
aforementioned events of the nineteenth century that were cited as quasi-nodal
points, we could find out that a thread links them despite the differences
between the scientific fields where their emergence occurred. Not only the
medical discourse that was articulated by phrenology and psychiatry, but also
both the statistical recordings and analyses that were developed by the rising
bureaucratic machine and the technical discovery of the arsenic’s retention,
had a theoretical perspective in common and shared the same historical
landscape. Shortly, this perspective was that of the concept of the Norm and
the landscape was shaped by the concepts of the Population and the
Individual.
How is this concept of the
Norm defined? Let us listen to Georges Canguilhem (1904 - 1995): “Littré and Robin’s Dictionnaire de medicine defines the normal as
follows: normal (normalis,
from norma,
rule): that which conforms to the rule, regular. The brevity of this entry in a
medical dictionary does not surprise us given the observations we have just
made. Lalande’s Vocabulaire technique et critique de la philosophie is more explicit. Since norma,
etymologically, means a T-square, normal is that which bends neither to the
right or left, hence that which remains in a happy medium; from which two
meanings are derived: (1) normal is that which is such that it ought to be; (2)
normal in the most usual sense of the word, is that which is met with in the
majority of cases of a determined kind, or that which constitutes either the
average or standard of a measurable characteristic”.[31] Consequently, the medical perspective should be combined with the technical and
critical perspective, if we want to see the emergence of the genealogical
formation of the concept of the Norm: that is, the T-square, the tool of the
professor of mathematics at high school, of the most iron-handed scientist in
the secondary education, but also the tool of the carpenter, of the technician
who has to square and set right what is by nature skewed, deviated and diverged
from the mean, that is, pathological. In fact, the pathological, not only as
the absolute Other of the Normal, but also as the mathematically and
quantitatively abnormal, is the perspective under which the sciences that paved
the way for criminology, put themselves. For, the penalty by including a double
reference, not only judicial (Law), but also physical (Norm), not only cultural
but also biological, attempted to attain and express the maximum “objectivity”.[32] Both
the psychiatric discourse that discovered in the brains of – in other respects
– normal individuals temporary states of insanity, which could lead to crime
and the cranioscopies conducted by Gall that
discovered the deviance either towards high or low of – in other respects –
normal tendencies, immanent to all people, or the statistical analyses of the
average mean that set limits of high and low, had as their goal the discovery
of the normal inside the abnormal or pathological. As Canguilhem claims, at the beginning of the eighteenth and towards the nineteenth century
we can see the formation, the constitution and establishment of a medical
theory concerning “the relations between the normal and the pathological,
according to which the pathological phenomena found in living organisms are
nothing more than quantitative variations, greater or lesser according to
corresponding physiological phenomena”.[33] Suffice
it to remind ourselves that the innovation of the Marsh test in regard to the
scan of arsenic abuts on the continuity between normality and abnormality, for
arsenic exists in the healthy human body as a trace element under normal
circumstances. That is, if its existence is too high, namely in abnormal
quantities, this would predicate an abnormal death.
Therefore,
we could easily understand the epistemological causes and reasons that pushed
Lombroso to photograph, both literally and metaphorically, the criminals that
he visited inside the cells not only of the prisons but also of the statistical
tables with which his books are filled. After all, Lombroso was clear and
unambiguous enough, and according to Hegel, very concrete: “The fundamental
proposition undoubtedly is that we ought to study not so much the abstract
crime as the criminal”,[34] confirming the significance that Foucault attributed to the shifting emphasis
of judicial and punitive power from the question concerning the circumstances
of the crime (“What must be punished and how?”) to the question concerning the
nature of the criminal (“Whom do you think you are punishing?”): “Legal justice
today has at least as much to do with criminals as with crimes. Or, more
precisely, though for a long time the criminal had been no more than the person
to whom a crime could be attributed and who could therefore be punished, today
the crime tends to be no more than the event that signals the existence of a
dangerous element – that is, more or less dangerous – in the social body”.[35] For the
crime breaks the law, but not the norm. On the contrary, the committed
crime conforms to a certain normality. If we would
like to explain and prevent it, we should turn our attention to the main causa causans,
according to Lombroso and his followers, of this normality, that is to the
abnormal individual, to the “born criminal”, who by his/her own nature cannot
be a subject of law but only an object of control. Following not the logic of
Law but that of the Norm, Lombroso classified into the category of abnormal
everyone that was not a “born criminal” but were “passionate criminals”, like
the political criminals and especially anarchists; the anarchists, according to
Lombroso, are characterized “on the one hand of an extreme sense of honesty and on the other of an hyper-sensitivity”.[36] For
those who tend to consider Lombroso as an extremely controversial figure in the
scientific field of criminology, we should remember Wertzell’s useful remark concerning the foundation of the Archiv für Kriminal-Anthropologie und Kriminalistik by
the Austrian judge Hans Gross in 1898: “That Gross used the term ‘criminal
anthropology’ in the journal’s title, even though he rejected Lombroso’s theory
of the born criminal as an anthropological type, reflected the continuing
influence of Lombrosian terminology”. Or that in 1913 Gross himself
“recommended the most extensive program of sterilization and castration with
the argument that society was in a desperate situation”.[37]
Law
and Norm
Therefore, in order to fully understand this
epistemological turn to the logic of the Norm, we should see on which
historical ground and horizon the scientific discourses that we have cited at
the beginning of this paper were rooted and fruited. Additionally, we should
keep in mind the fact that already since the eighteenth century both the
population and the individuals were objects of state providence par excellence.
Besides, the term “statistics” owes its very existence to the German Professor
of Philosophy and Law Gottfried Achenwall (1719-1772), who coined this term (Staatistik), meaning statecraft,
in order to describe “catalogues and surveys illustrating ‘the condition and
prospects of society’ ”.[38] Thus,
it is not surprising that “when the University of Heidelberg celebrated its
400th anniversary in 1786, it was the new school of state administration {Staatswirthschaft} that captured much of the
attention”.[39] However, what is it that a state really and actually needs to know, so as to be
capable of setting out and establishing a policy based on scientific knowledge
of the condition and prospects of a society? If we make an attempt to listen
once again – perhaps more carefully or more concretely this time – to Hegel and
his remarks, the state should know everything that concerns the individual. If
we then take into consideration Foucault’s remarks we could see that the
scientific knowledge of the individual presupposes and is founded upon the
non-abstract knowledge of the population forming a circulus vitiosus: “The final objective is the population. The
population is pertinent as the objective, and individuals, the series of
individuals, are no longer pertinent as the objective, but simply as the
instrument, relay, or condition for obtaining something at the level of
population”.[40] Consequently,
“the population is not, then, a collection of juridical subjects
in an individual or collective relationship with a sovereign will. It is a set
of elements in which we can note constants and regularities even in accidents,
in which we can identify the universal of desire regularly producing the
benefit of all, and with regard to which we can identify a number of modifiable
variables on which it depends”.[41]
Crime, therefore, was the
missing link between the knowledge of the individual and the knowledge of
population. Thus, it should not surprise us that in 1838 the French Academy of
Sciences awarded the prize of the best treatise to Honoré-Antoine Frégier (1789 – 1860), the Police Administrator of
the region of Seine, who gave the eloquent title Des classes dangereuses de la population dans les grandes villes, et des moyens de les rendre meilleures (On
dangerous classes of population in the great cities and on the mediums of their
amelioration) to a content that does honour to the best moments of the
French spirit, at least, as it was expressed during the infamous “Great
Confinement” (1656). Let us remind ourselves that the Foucauldian term “Great Confinement”, which has its origin in his groundbreaking and seminal work on the history of madness (1961), describes “the structure
most clearly visible in the classical experience of madness, and because it is
that practice of confinement that would suddenly seem so scandalous when the
experience came to disappear from European culture”. More precisely, “[a]
single date serves as a reference point here. In Paris in 1656, the Hôpital Général was set up by a royal decree”. This structure,
according to Foucault, represents at the historical level the exclusion of madness by reason, which had
taken place in 1647 at the philosophical level by the “holy figure” of modern philosophy, René Descartes in his First Meditation. Thus, madmen are now
the target of a confinement, since confinement is a generalized practice
against every individual that fails to conform to the social norms:
prostitutes, vagrants, blasphemers, etc. Given that during the seventeenth
century, 1% of the population in Paris is confined, as “[t]he 1656 edict
addressed a quite undifferentiated mass made up of a population with no
resources and no social moorings”, Foucault claims that “[t]he practice of
confinement demonstrates a new reaction to poverty and indigence, a strange,
novel form of pathos, a different relationship between mankind and all that can
be inhuman in his existence. In the course of [the] sixteenth century, the
figure of pauper, and those who could not be responsible for their own
existence, gradually assumed a role that the Middle Ages would have failed to recognize altogether”.[42]Almost
two centuries later, Frégier’s treatise on the
dangerous classes resonates the transformations and
the distinctions that Foucault described regarding madness. Let us cite only a
phrase in which the author characterizes and categorizes as dangerous classes,
“the gambler, the prostitutes, their lovers and their pimps, their madams, the
vagabonds, the swindlers and the crooks, the twisters and the thieves, the
shoplifters and the fences”.[43] This
treatise is recognized as a valuable work and a milestone in the preface of the Crime Classification Manual (CCM),
FBI’s manual that in 1992 replaced the Diagnostic
and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders (DSM), concerning the
“classification system for serial sexual murder”.[44] However, it should be noted here, that DSM is still considered to be a valid –
in scientific terms – a source of categorization and diagnosis of the criminal,
that is, their anti-social or abnormal behaviour. As it is clearly and
evidently expressed by contemporary criminologists when they face the problem
of anti-social behaviour: “It is anticipated that the DSM-5 will be published
in May 2013 so one will need to wait to see exactly how antisocial personality disorder is defined at that time and whether
the traditional personality features of psychopathy will be prominently featured”.[45]
Thus,
the crime, that is, the criminal, as a factor not only of subversion of law and justice but also of the derangement and disturbance of normality and normativity, that is not only as an illegal but also as a dangerous agent, became the object of
control by the modern relations of power and knowledge. In fact, this is a
rupture in the confrontation with danger and its vehicle. Speaking rather
schematically in regards to the control of individuals, whereas until the
seventeenth century the prevailing model had been that of the leper and
leprosy, namely, that of the control of the individual who is exiled, who
should be excluded, driven out in order to purify the community, since the
eighteenth century a model as old as the previous one has been reactivated and
become prevalent: the model of the plague and the plague-infested towns. Whereas
the model of leprosy is based on the exclusion and needs the Law in order to
function properly, the model of plague is based on inclusion and needs other
than the Law and the power of the Norm. Thenceforth, political and medical
power are not confronted with the legal rights or the legal substance of the
leper, in order to answer the question if he/she is or not a member of the community,
but they are confronted with the norms of control and therapy of the plague
victim in order to deal with the problem of how he/she could be healed inside
the community without risking the latter’s prosperity. The patient is no more
excluded and expelled out of the town; on the contrary, he/she is included and
confined in order to be under control more effectively. Instead of the distance
that leprosy demanded, the plague demands proximity and stability of
observation and control by the medical gaze. Instead of the permanent and
definitive stigmatisation of leprosy, we can note the constant control of the
plague-infested town according to the norms of health and to health
regulations. From the exclusion of the individual aiming at the purification of
the population we have passed to the care for the social body through the
control of the individual’s body.[46] Nonetheless, scarcely had the new model or mechanism – let us call it
disciplinary –been established than one could already note the emergence of
something different due to a new danger.
The
smallpox epidemic was the greatest danger during the eighteenth century, as the
2/3 children were infected with a mortality rate of 1 in 7.782, that is, almost
1/8.[47] However, in 1718 Lady Mary Wortley Montagu (1689 – 1762), wife of the British
Ambassador in Istanbul, Sir Edward
Wortley Montagu (1678 - 1761), introduced to Europe from the Ottoman
Empire the method of inoculation or variolisation for smallpox.[48] As
Foucault eloquently and profoundly remarks, inoculation was characterized by
four novice and significant elements: it is absolutely preventative, it has
almost total certainty of success, it is in principle able to be extended to
the whole population at low cost and, finally, but most importantly,
inoculation was completely foreign to any medical theory, as it was
“unthinkable in terms of medical rationality of this time”, as “it was a pure
matter of fact, of the most naked empiricism, and this remained the case until
the middle of the nineteenth century, roughly with Pasteur, when medicine was
able to provide a rational understanding of the phenomenon”.[49] The new
formation does not make a distinction between healthy and sick individuals; on
the contrary, it addresses the whole population, for it is under threat on the
basis of probabilities. Furthermore, in the interior of the population, this
novice formation distinguishes groups of people with higher probable mortality,
such as infants, and groups with lesser, adults, and thus attempts to bridge
the distance between them in order to construct a normal mortality rate, that
is, the Norm.[50] Whereas the disciplinary model is based more on the repression and the
exclusion of the individual, the new model – let us call it the security one –
displaces the emphasis onto the prediction and prevention of danger.
Conclusion
If someone keeps wondering what relationship do
all the aforementioned cases have with Criminology and Law, we should remember
that at the First International Conference of Criminal Anthropology, in Rome in
1885, the Belgian criminologist Adolphe Prins (1845 – 1919) introduced the concept of “social
defence”, emphasizing the question not of the level of the criminal’s responsibility, but of the level of the danger that he/she constitutes for the
society,[51] although
the Italian jurist Giovanni Carmignani (1768 – 1847)
had already made the same movement since 1831.[52] Thus,
before Nazism became the synonym of racism, western rationality through its
scientific discourse under the pretext of “social defence” had already called
for the sterilization of people with a ‘‘pronounced criminal disposition’’ and
of all who suffered from incurable, supposedly hereditary, diseases including
epilepsy, tuberculosis, cancer, syphilis, and alcoholism.[53] Also,
we should remind ourselves that in 1887 Sherlock Holmes, the most famous detective, came into existence through
the typewriter of the physician Sir
Arthur Conan Doyle (1859 – 1930). Holmes’ character was based on the
characters, on the one hand, of the Professor of Medicine Joseph Bell (1837 – 1911) and on the other of the
Professor of Forensics and police doctor Sir Henry Duncan
Littlejohn (1826 – 1914),[54] as a
literal incarnation of the historical substitution of penalty for the crime,
according to the Law, by the scientific knowledge of the criminal, according to
the Norm, in the context of a discourse, which is simultaneously both medical and judicial, both about security and about justice, both about norm and about right. If someone takes a critical and careful look at the history
of western societies, he/she might say in turn: “Elementary, my dear Watchon”.
* National and Kapodistrian University of Athens.
[2] Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, “Who thinks
abstractly?” in Walter Kaufmann, Hegel:
Texts and Commentary, (Garden City, NY: Anchor Books, 1966), pp. 113-118.
[3] Hans Gross, Criminal
Investigation. A practical handbook for magistrates, police officers and
lawyers, tr. J. Adam & J. Collyer – Adam, (Madras: A. Krishnamahari, 1906), p. 32.
[4] Gross, Criminal Investigation, p. 27: “We may remind our readers that the
subject with which this book deals in part, Criminal
Phenomenology, is but one branch of the wider science of Criminology”.
[5] Cesare Lombroso, The
Criminal Man, (New York and London: G. P. Putnam,1911).
[6] David Macey, The Lives of Michel
Foucault, (New York: Vintage Books, 1993), p. 248.
[7] See Michel Foucault (ed.), I Pierre Riviere, having slaughtered my
mother, my sister, and my brother: A case of parricide in the 19th century, tr. F. Jellinek, (New York: Random
House, 1975), p. xi.
[8] Richard F. Wetzell, Inventing the Criminal. A History of
German Criminology, 1880-1945, (Chapel Hill
and London: The University of North Carolina Press, 2000), p. 19.
[9] Wetzell, Inventing the Criminal, p. 20.
[10] Michel Foucault, Abnormal,
Lectures at the Collège de France, 1974-5, tr.
Gr. Burchell (New York: Picador, 2003), p.32.
[11] Michel Foucault, “The Politics of Health in the
Eighteenth Century”, in Michel Foucault, Essential
Works, 1954-1984, vol. 3, Power, (ed.) J. D. Faubion,
tr. by R. Hurley, (London: Penguin, 2002), p. 94.
[12] Michel Foucault, “Omnes et Singulatim”, in Michel Foucault, Essential Works, 1954-1984, vol. 3, Power, p. 323.
[13] Andre Wakefield, The Disordered Police State, German Cameralism as Science and Practice, p. 74.
[14] Wakefield, The Disordered Police State, p. 92.
[15] See Michel Foucault, Discipline and Punish, The
Birth of the Prison, tr. A. Sheridan, (London: Penguin, 1991), p. 197.
[16] See Grégoire Chamayou, (2013). “Fichte’s Passport: A
Philosophy of the Police”, tr. A. Kieran, Theory and Event 16(2).
[17] Michel Foucault, “The Birth of Social Medicine”, in
Michel Foucault, Essential Works,
1954-1984, vol. 3, Power, p. 140.
[18] Michel Foucault, Security,
Territory, Population, Lectures at the Collège de
France, 1977-8, tr. G. Burchell, (New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2007), pp. 337-8. Also,
Andrew Johnson (2014), ”Foucault: Critical Theory of
the Police in a Neoliberal Age”, Theoria, 141 (4), pp. 5-29.
[19] Foucault, Security, 1977-8, pp. 107-8.
[20] Michel Foucault, The History of Sexuality: Volume 1: An Introduction, trans. R. Hurley, (New York: Vintage Books, 1978) p.
144.
[21] See Dorothy Porter, Health, Civilization and the State. A History of Public Health from
ancient to modern times, (London: Routledge, 1999), pp. 64-66.
[22] Quoted in A. M. Davis, “Tailoring and the normal
body”, in E. Waltraud (ed.), Histories of the Normal and the Abnormal. Social and Cultural Histories
of Norms and Normativity, (New York: Routledge, 2006), p. 143.
[23] Ιan Hacking, “How
should we do the history of statistics?”, in Graham Burchell, Colin Gordon & Peter Miller (ed.), The Foucault Effect, Studies in
Governmentality, (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1991) pp. 181-195. Also, Ann F. La Berge, Mission and Method, The early nineteenth-century French public health
movement, (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1992), pp. 55-7.
[24] Wetzell, Inventing the Criminal, p. 21.
[25] See W. G. Rothstein, Public
Health and the Risk Factor. A History of an Uneven Medical Revolution, (New
York: University of Rochester Press, 2003), p. 23.
[26] Ιan Hacking, “How should we do the history of
statistics?”, pp. 187-8.
[27] Hacking, “How
should we do the history of statistics?”, p. 192.
[28] Wetzell, Inventing the Criminal, pp. 22-3. Also, E. McLaughlin
& J. Muncie (ed.), The Sage Dictionary of Criminology,
(London: Sage, 2001), pp. 132-3.
[29] Rothstein, Public
Health, p. 28.
[30] James C. Whorton, The Arsenic Century. How Victorian Britain was
poisoned at Home, Work and Play, (Oxford and New York: Oxford University
Press, 2010), pp. 82-3.
[31] Georges Canguilhem, The Normal and the Pathological, tr. C.
R. Fawcett & R. S. Cohen, (New York: Zone Books, 1991), p. 125.
[32] Foucault, Discipline
and Punish, pp. 170-184.
[33] Canguilhem, The Normal and the Pathological, p. 42.
[34] Cesare Lombroso, Crime,
Its Causes and Remedies, tr. H. P. Horton, (London: W. Heinemann, 1911), p. 365.
[35] Foucault, “About the concept
of ’Dangerous Individual’”, in Michel Foucault, Essential Works, 1954-1984, vol. 3, Power, pp. 178-9.
[36] Cesare Lombroso, The Anarchists, tr. T. Bouzanis,
(Ioannina: Isnafi, 2011), p. 80. See Wetzell, Inventing the Criminal, pp. 61 and 104.
[37] See Wetzell, Inventing the
Criminal, pp. 61 and
104.
[38] Porter, Health,
Civilization and the State, p. 49.
[39] Wakefield, The Disordered Police
State, p. 131.
[40] Foucault, Security, 1977-8, p. 42.
[41] Foucault, Security,
1977-8, p. 74.
[42] See Michel
Foucault, History of Madness, J. Khalfa (ed.), tr. J. Murphy & J. Khalfa,
(London & New York: Routledge), pp. 44 - 77.
[43] Honoré Antoine Frégier, Des classes
dangereuses de la population dans les grandes villes, et des moyens de les
rendre meilleures, (Paris: B. Baillière, 1840), p. 44. Also Wetzell, Inventing the
Criminal, pp. 27-8.
[44] John Douglas,
Ann W. Burgess, Allen G. Burgess, & Robert K. Ressler (ed.), Crime Classification Manual, (Jossey – Bass, 2006),
pp.3 and 98.
[45] See Gerben Bruisma & David Weisburd (ed.), Encyclopaedia of Criminology and Criminal
Justice, (New York, Heidelberg, Dordrecht, London: Springer, 2014) pp.
4124-5 (emphasis added).
[46] Foucault, Abnormal, 1974-5, pp. 43-5.
[47] Foucault, Security,
1977-8, p. 58.
[48] Porter, Health, p. 56.
[49] Foucault, Security,
1977-8, p. 58.
[50] Foucault, Security, 1977-8, pp. 62-3.
[51] Foucault, “About the concept of
‘Dangerous Individual’”, in Michel Foucault, Essential Works, 1954-1984, vol. 3, Power, p. 190.
[52] E. McLaughlin & J. Muncie (ed.), The Sage Dictionary of Criminology, p. 272-4. Also, P. Pasquino, “Criminology: The Birth of a special Knowledge”,
in G. Burchell, C. Gordon & P. Miller (ed.), The Foucault Effect, Studies in
Governmentality, pp. 235-50.
[53] Wetzell, Inventing the Criminal, p. 104.
[54] E. J. Wagner, The Science of
Sherlock Holmes. From Baskerville Hall to the Valley of Fear. The real Forensics behind the great detectives cases, (Wiley,
2006), pp. 54-60.
|
 |
|
 |
|
|
|
|
|
|
past issues
> Vol.8, Fall 2013
> Vol.7, Spring 2013
> Vol.6, Fall 2012
> Vol.5, Spring 2012
> Vol.4, Fall 2010 > Vol.3, Fall 2009 > Vol.2, Fall 2008
> Vol.1, Summer 2007
events
> 2012/13 HoST Seminars
> past events
submissions
> guidelines for authors
> instructions for book reviewers
about the journal
> about the journal
> editorial board
rss feeds
> rss feeds
|
 |